Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy
Simone Weil is an often-overlooked thinker whose insights could radically reshape contemporary discourses on religion, nature, art, ethics, work, politics, and education. This collection of essays situates Simone Weil’s thought alongside prominent Continental thinkers and their philosophical concerns to show the ways in which she belongs to—but also stands outside—some of the major streams of 'Continental discourse', including phenomenology, ethics of embodied disposition and difference, and post-Marxian political thought. For the first time in a major work, intersections between the ideas of Weil and figures such as Nietzsche, Berdyaev, Foucault, Blanchot, Merleau-Ponty, Levinas, Chrétien, Agamben, Fanon, and Rancière are closely examined. The volume is authored by an international team of leading scholars in Weil studies and in contemporary Continental philosophy of religion more broadly. Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy is not only an unprecedented resource for Weil scholars who seek to read her in broader (and more current) philosophical terms, but also an important addition to the libraries of scholars and students of Continental philosophy and theology engaged in thinking about some of the most pressing questions of our time.
1300555371
Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy
Simone Weil is an often-overlooked thinker whose insights could radically reshape contemporary discourses on religion, nature, art, ethics, work, politics, and education. This collection of essays situates Simone Weil’s thought alongside prominent Continental thinkers and their philosophical concerns to show the ways in which she belongs to—but also stands outside—some of the major streams of 'Continental discourse', including phenomenology, ethics of embodied disposition and difference, and post-Marxian political thought. For the first time in a major work, intersections between the ideas of Weil and figures such as Nietzsche, Berdyaev, Foucault, Blanchot, Merleau-Ponty, Levinas, Chrétien, Agamben, Fanon, and Rancière are closely examined. The volume is authored by an international team of leading scholars in Weil studies and in contemporary Continental philosophy of religion more broadly. Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy is not only an unprecedented resource for Weil scholars who seek to read her in broader (and more current) philosophical terms, but also an important addition to the libraries of scholars and students of Continental philosophy and theology engaged in thinking about some of the most pressing questions of our time.
43.99 In Stock
Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy

Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy

by A. Rebecca Rozelle-Stone (Editor)
Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy

Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy

by A. Rebecca Rozelle-Stone (Editor)

eBook

$43.99 

Available on Compatible NOOK devices, the free NOOK App and in My Digital Library.
WANT A NOOK?  Explore Now

Related collections and offers

LEND ME® See Details

Overview

Simone Weil is an often-overlooked thinker whose insights could radically reshape contemporary discourses on religion, nature, art, ethics, work, politics, and education. This collection of essays situates Simone Weil’s thought alongside prominent Continental thinkers and their philosophical concerns to show the ways in which she belongs to—but also stands outside—some of the major streams of 'Continental discourse', including phenomenology, ethics of embodied disposition and difference, and post-Marxian political thought. For the first time in a major work, intersections between the ideas of Weil and figures such as Nietzsche, Berdyaev, Foucault, Blanchot, Merleau-Ponty, Levinas, Chrétien, Agamben, Fanon, and Rancière are closely examined. The volume is authored by an international team of leading scholars in Weil studies and in contemporary Continental philosophy of religion more broadly. Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy is not only an unprecedented resource for Weil scholars who seek to read her in broader (and more current) philosophical terms, but also an important addition to the libraries of scholars and students of Continental philosophy and theology engaged in thinking about some of the most pressing questions of our time.

Product Details

ISBN-13: 9781786601339
Publisher: Dutton Penguin Group USA
Publication date: 11/08/2017
Sold by: Barnes & Noble
Format: eBook
Pages: 272
File size: 594 KB
Age Range: 18 Years

About the Author

Rebecca Rozelle-Stone is an Associate Professor of Philosophy and the Director of Women and Gender Studies at the University of North Dakota. She is an active member of the American Weil Society and served as its President from 2014-2016. She is co-editor of The Relevance of the Radical: Simone Weil 100 Years Later (2009) and co-author of Simone Weil and Theology (2013).
Rebecca Rozelle-Stone is Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of Women and Gender Studies at the University of North Dakota. She is President of the American Weil Society, co-editor of The Relevance of the Radical: Simone Weil 100 Years Later (2009) and co-author of Simone Weil and Theology (2013).

Read an Excerpt

CHAPTER 1

Weil's Boat

On Becoming and Being

Philip Goodchild

A recurrent image of the human condition used in the writings of Simone Weil is that of a sailor in a boat:

The intelligence is powerless to get its bearings amid the innumerable eddies formed by wind and water on the high seas; but if we place in the midst of these swirling waters a boat whose sails and rudder are fixed in such and such a manner it is possible to draw up a list of the actions which they can cause it to undergo. (OL 88)

The rudder symbolizes both human reason and moral self-determination. Here, human will and intelligence seem to be alone sufficient to navigate through the flux: the will operates amid temporal change by setting its own orientation. Yet by Weil's late work, the boat has capsized:

We are like shipwrecked persons clinging to logs upon the sea and tossed in an entirely passive manner by every movement of the waves. From the height of heaven God throws each one a rope. He who seizes the rope and does not let go, despite the pain and the fear, remains as much as the others subject to the buffeting of the waves; only for him these buffets combine with the tension of the cord to form a different mechanical whole. (ICG 194)

In Weil's later work, the moral will has been replaced by consent, and work by attention. Humanism has been replaced by supernatural grace: the human being may only find a secure anchor in the sky. If the rudder symbolizes morality, the crucial question for understanding Weil is this: what does the rope symbolize? Is this a return from practical philosophy to metaphysics? Has the sailor been rescued from the sea of temporal becoming by grace from the sky of eternal being? Or, on the contrary, is the supernatural only encountered, grasped, and conceived in and through the temporal?

The traditional philosophical distinction between being and becoming can be used to distinguish between two kinds of philosophy: there is a philosophy of being, a theoretical exercise that seeks to determine either the essence of things as in the metaphysical tradition, which derives from Plato and Aristotle, or the essence of reason as in the critical tradition, which derives from Descartes and Kant, or seeks simply to judge what is the case as in the analytic tradition, which derives from Frege and Russell; there is also a philosophy of becoming, which might take inspiration from the pre-Socratics but has emerged out of the Romantic historicization of reason by Schelling and Hegel. This "continental philosophy" takes many forms: it might concern itself with inwardness and existence, as in Kierkegaard and Sartre, or with material sensation and action, as in Feuerbach and Marx, or with phenomena and meaning, as in Husserl and Gadamer. Yet what is distinctive about this philosophy is that it is grounded no longer in a thought supposed pure, true, and implicitly divine, but in changeable life: it culminates in the radical postmetaphysical tradition. Substance, morality, and logic no longer offer a stable orientation amid the flux. Following Nietzsche's proclamation of the innocence of becoming from judgment by being, Heidegger's analysis of the temporality of being was extended into the diverse philosophies of difference found in Levinas, Derrida, Deleuze, Foucault, Irigaray, and many others.

If radical continental philosophy can be broadly characterized as a philosophy of becoming, then the received wisdom about Weil is that she takes a stand against the tide of becoming as an unrepentant Christian Platonist. Her rejection of progress in philosophy sets her against modernity with its cult of creation of the new. Whether one judges that she is essentially Christian, Platonic, Pythagorean, Stoic, Gnostic, or Manichaean, her main sources of inspiration are not often regarded as modern. Her distance from the Nietzschean tradition of naturalism seems more extreme: Weil appeals to supernatural inspiration as her source of truth. She is often regarded primarily as a religious thinker, and not a philosopher at all: for it is such private visions or inspirations that were excluded from the domain of reason by Hume and Kant because they are not universalizable. Consequently, the main emphasis of Weil scholarship lies in giving an account of her mystical doctrine, the "religious philosophy" that she revealed in the final three years of her life. Under this assumption, radical continental thought, with its preoccupation for extending the critique of reason to expose the pretensions, lacunae, and bids for power of modernist thought, could have little more than superficial contact with Weil.

What places do being and becoming really hold in her thought? To investigate, first we will clarify the radical critique of philosophies of being, taking Nietzsche as a key representative, as well as clarify the critique of Nietzsche offered by Weil. The aim, here, is not to take sides but to expose the mutual contradiction. Next, I will summarize her philosophy of temporality to see if it offers any grounds for rapprochement. For, on the one hand, Weil has a critique of timeless, theoretical truth comparable to those of the philosophies of becoming; on the other hand, she also has a critique of the historicality of being and notions of historical progress (LPr 29). Weil resolves the contradiction through a change in level, a motion symbolized by her rope. For the specific relations between time and eternity, becoming and being, the natural and supernatural that she constructs in her notion of "grace" require an elevation of perspective beyond these simple oppositions.

ASCETICISM AND FORCE: A MUTUAL CRITIQUE

The Nietzschean critique of Christian Platonism is well known. Nietzsche protested against an implicit conceptual idolatry that falsifies reality in conserving static concepts alone: "They kill, they stuff, when they worship, these conceptual idolaters — they become a mortal danger to everything when they worship. Death, change, age, as well as procreation and growth, are for them objections — refutations even. What is, does not become; what becomes, is not." He claims that such concepts as the unconditioned, the good, the true, and the perfect lack a clearly defined sense: they are the most general, thinnest, and emptiest of concepts. Since one lacks access to these concepts, moral words such as justice, wisdom, holiness, and virtue are invoked to judge and condemn all that may be blamed for preventing human access to them, but this is merely revenge against the complex, subtle, nuanced, and self-contradicting ways of the human spirit. Morality itself, for Nietzsche, is antinature. The question of the value of morality is only raised when situated in relation to its value for life. "Why have morality at all when life, nature and history are 'not moral'?" Morality is invoked against nature as a denial or refusal of natural desires and powers and yet morality must have been produced by life. Given this evaluation in relation to life, Nietzsche is able to assimilate all moralism to the supernatural as epitomized by Platonism:

One would have to be situated outside life, and on the other hand to know it as thoroughly as any, as many, as all who have experienced it, to be permitted to touch on the problem of the value of life at all: sufficient reason for understanding that this problem is for us an inaccessible problem. When we speak of values we do so under the inspiration and from the perspective of life: life itself evaluates through us when we establish values.

Nietzsche condemns the pretension to imitate or participate in a position of transcendent judgment, outside of life; he diagnoses it as the product of a declining, debilitated life, seeking to survive by condemning others. Yet this conceptual move of assimilating morality to the supernatural is possible only as a correlate of assimilating the evaluative power of the mind to life itself: the mind is merely a product of the forces that operate through it. This devaluation of consciousness is achieved by elevating the immanent power of life itself. Life is understood as evaluative power, as will and will is understood by what it does, by force. Lacking the qualitative discrimination afforded by a moral view of life, life can only be understood in quantitative terms as will to power. For its reality is given by its action, and not by any appearance to consciousness; qualitative distinctions are now only to be made between active and reactive forces. Active forces go to the limit of what they can do, while reactive forces, upon which consciousness is based, express their moral vision of life by condemning the active powers of nature.

Nietzsche, therefore, has offered a basis for the radical continental tradition to condemn the false consciousness or self-deception that appears in any appeal to the moral, the supernatural, or an ascetic ideal. For many, Weil's life and thought would epitomize all that the Nietzscheans protest against. As a cure for self-despair, Nietzsche recommends the self-affirmation of life or amor fati:

My formula for greatness in a human being is amor fati: that one wants nothing to be other than it is, not in the future, not in the past, not in all eternity. Not merely to endure that which happens of necessity, still less to dissemble it — all idealism is untruthfulness in the face of necessity — but to love it.

This would appear to be the self-affirmation of force by force, but it is a force that transforms itself by its own self-affirmation. Insofar as reality is composed of such active, self-affirmative forces, then it is composed of self-transformation, of becoming: what is real becomes; what simply is, is not real. This, in brief, is the Nietzschean perspective: its protest against philosophies of being is that they both lack content (appealing to vague, general concepts) and that they lack power, failing to express the self-transformative power of life.

What is less well known is the conceptual underpinning of Weil's critique of Nietzsche. Like Nietzsche, Weil begins her account of society with nature and plurality. In human life, nature makes itself felt through the compulsion of need, and there is an unlimited diversity of individuals together with their capacities for innovation. She adds to these the Darwinian notion of "conditions of existence": only those behaviors that adapt to natural pressures and social competition survive. In other words, a force which goes too far, which does not operate within limits, will undermine its own conditions of existence. For human beings in society, these "conditions of existence" include specifically the organization of means of production and weapons, of methods of work and warfare. Some of these are of such complexity as to be the privilege of a few: Weil cites explicitly religious rites, arms, and money (OL 64). Through possessing these means, natural force is translated into human obedience, for continued existence relies on complex conditions of existence. Yet natural and social forces differ in kind. Natural force is entirely present; social force depends on threat and promise, on anticipation of the future. Weil then formulates her own theory of the will to power, but one which is exclusively concerned with social relations of privilege, obedience, and oppression, rather than with natural force:

The preservation of power is a vital necessity for the powerful, since it is their power which provides their sustenance; but they have to preserve it both against their rivals and against their inferiors, and these latter cannot do otherwise than try to rid themselves of dangerous masters; for, through a vicious circle, the master produces fear in the slave by the very fact that he is afraid of him, and vice versa; and the same is true between rival powers. (OL 65)

This situation of rivalry simply does not apply in the relations between humanity and nature: although humans feel the pressure of natural necessity, and nature offers resistance and obstacles to their efforts, even so, nature does not defend itself. Natural necessity is a struggle contained within real limits, and the resistance and obstacles it offers may be turned into means toward a goal: "The wind consents to guide to her destination the same ship which it would have sent off her course if sails and rudder had not properly been adjusted" (OL 66-67). By contrast, social rivalry is in principle unlimited (WA 194). The limit of power won over others would be their extermination, but to exterminate one's slaves is to exterminate one's own power; to exterminate one's rivals is to exterminate one's own prestige. Power is essentially unstable:

For, owing to the fact that there is never power, but only a race for power, and that there is no term, no limit, no proportion set to this race, neither is there any limit or proportion set to the efforts that it exacts; those who give themselves up to it, compelled to do always better than their rivals, who in their turn strive to do better than they, must sacrifice not only the existence of the slaves, but their own also and that of their nearest and dearest. (OL 67-68)

Nevertheless, there is no escape under these conditions of existence: even if the masters dream of moderation, they can only practice it at the risk of defeat.

Weil can be quite consistent, therefore, in accepting moral suspicion: social morality, like religious rites, is another "condition of existence" manipulated in the quest for power. Indeed, she translates Plato to the effect that the true sophists are the moralists who complain about the corruption of others, who blame and praise:

What individual education could resist and not be submerged and swept away in the torrent of blame and praise? So he [the individual] will decide, according to the opinions of others, that certain things are beautiful and certain others disgraceful; he will share the same pursuits as the others, and become like them. — The compulsion would be powerful, Socrates — And yet, said Socrates, I have still not mentioned the strongest compulsion — What is it? — The compulsion exerted by these educators, these sophists, on those whom they fail to persuade. Don't you know that they punish with disgraces and fines and death those who resist their persuasion?

For there is not, there never has been, and there never will be, any other moral teaching except that of public opinion. At least, no other human teaching; the divine, as the proverb says, is an exception to all rules. (SNLG 98)

Like Nietzsche, Weil starts with a radical moral skepticism: there is no representation of Platonic ideas (N 2 418-19, 455, 545). Yet for her, knowledge only comes with resistance: human beings "are so made that the ones who do the crushing feel nothing; it is the person who is crushed who feels what is happening" (LP 139). From a Weilienne perspective, Nietzsche has made two fundamental errors: one, the error of transporting the unlimited principle of social disequilibrium, the struggle for power, into the sphere of nature itself, where force is strictly limited by the conditions of its existence; the other is that he makes the principle of affirmation, the will that affirms itself, into an active principle, and yet this is simply the principle of praise and blame, of moral judgment once more. Even in Nietzsche's transvaluation of all values, the values may have been changed but the occupation of the crowd is still present: Nietzsche remains a moralist insofar as his books are filled with judgments of praise and blame. The crowd, as Weil argues, falls back on praise and blame because there is no such thing as collective thought. For what thought grasps is always relation and necessity, and this requires an individual mind; for example, the number two in one person's mind can never be added to the number two in another's to make four. So while Nietzsche may claim to diagnose the underlying will to power manifest in any particular symptom of life, his diagnoses have no compulsion, no necessity, and no inner clarity: a judgment in Nietzsche's mind is not a rational necessity for his readers. From Weil's perspective, therefore, he falls short of the Cartesian method.

(Continues…)



Excerpted from "Simone Weil and Continental Philosophy"
by .
Copyright © 2017 A. Rebecca Rozelle-Stone.
Excerpted by permission of Rowman & Littlefield International, Ltd..
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Table of Contents

Introduction: Attending to the Outlaw A. Rebecca Rozelle-Stone / Part I: Transcendental and Embodied Crossings / 1. Weil’s Boat: On Becoming and Being Philip Goodchild / 2.“Strangely Surprised”: Maurice Blanchot on Simone Weil Kevin Hart / 3. Decreation and the Creative Act: Simone Weil and Nikolai Berdyaev Lisa Radakovich Holsberg / 4. Recreating the Creature: Weil, Agamben, Animality & the Unsaveable Beatrice Marovich / Part II: Attentive Ethics / 5. Attention and Expression: Prescriptive and Descriptive Philosophy in Weil and Merleau-Ponty Kascha Semonovitch Snavely / 6. Levinas and Weil: Ethics after Auschwitz Robert Reed / 7. Compassion, Consolation, and the Sharing of Attention Stuart Jesson / 8: Simone Weil and the Problem of Fatigue A. Rebecca Rozelle-Stone / Part III: Emancipatory Politics / 9: Simone Weil’s Analysis of Oppression: From La Boétie to the Neoliberal PresentLissa McCullough / 10. The Training of the Soul: Simone Weil’s Dialectical Disciplinary Paradigm, a reading alongside Michel Foucault Scott B. Ritner / 11. “To love human beings in so far as they are nothing”: Deracination and Pessimism in Weil Anthony Paul Smith / 12. Weil and Rancière on Attention and Emancipation Sophie Bourgault
From the B&N Reads Blog

Customer Reviews